The historical caution in philosophy towards images was shaped by
Plato's view that art and images are distorted versions of the
"ideal" from the rational realm, considered superior to our sensory
world. However, the modern age's intellectual and artistic shifts highlighted
the significance of sensory existence and imagination, especially in artistic
creation. Science further validated the role of the observable and imagination
in creation. This emphasis, along with other factors, paved the way for today's
digital era, where images are paramount in communication. Moving beyond the
Platonic view, there's a heightened philosophical focus on the role of images
in life, especially in the media and visual arts. This is evident in
discussions linking advertisement as part of media with philosophy and the
reliance on the implicit knowledge through which the participants perceive the
“real,” including the world. This is also evident in discussions linking the
painting with philosophy and the use of artworks, like Paul Cézanne's, as cited
by Merleau-Ponty, for philosophical insights. Figures such as Freud, Deleuze,
Foucault, and Heidegger exemplify the merger of art and philosophy,
representing a "philosophical nomadism" inspired by Nietzsche. This
blending is driven by cultural and intellectual evolutions, highlighting the
fluidity between art, philosophy, and science.
Foucault's fascination with surrealist painter René Magritte extended
beyond their personal friendship to a shared intellectual curiosity, especially
regarding the relationship between words and objects. Both held similar
perspectives on the world, human existence, and their respective mediums of
expression. While Foucault utilized an archaeological method to dissect human
actions in history, Magritte's surrealist approach allowed him to delve deep
into subjects, reconstructing and exploring their meanings. Magritte's
drawings, influenced by encounters with philosophical works like
Merleau-Ponty's 'Phenomenology of Perception', Perelman's writings, and
Foucault's 'The Order of Things', became platforms for philosophical
expression, albeit in an aesthetic manner. Despite deriving his style from
surrealism and being significantly influenced by the Italian painter Giorgio de
Chirico, Magritte's art was infused with philosophical content, transforming
images into thought-provoking problems. Philosophers, including Foucault, thus
recognized Magritte's paintings as potent exemplars for discussing intellectual
and cultural subjects, with Foucault even penning a book on the art of drawing
in relation to Magritte. René Magritte often placed familiar objects in surreal
contexts, as seen in his renowned drawing "The Treachery of Images"
or “La trahison des images” (Fig1). This drawing depicts a pipe with the
caption "This is not a pipe", underscoring that an image isn't the
actual object. Magritte says about this particular painting: "The famous
pipe. How people reproached me for it! And yet, could you stuff my pipe? No,
it's just a representation, isn't it? So if I had written in my picture 'This
is a pipe', I'd have been lying!" Magritte's commentary is a classic
reflection on semiotics, the study of signs and symbols, and their use or
interpretation.
Figure 1: the “La trahison des
images” by René Magritte (1928-29)
Magritte was influenced by philosophical
interactions, notably with Bierleman and Foucault. Foucault's 1973 book
"This is not a pipe" analyzed Magritte's works, emphasizing the
"resemblance" problem and the image-object relationship, questioning
thought-reality alignment and truth's nature. Their works bridge the historical
gap, initiated by Plato, between image and truth. Magritte's 1929 piece
"The Treachery of Images" confronted this skepticism, suggesting that
while images may deceive, seeking a "truer" reality is unreasonable.
After his painting "The Selective Affinities" in 1932, Magritte
clearly distinguished himself from surrealism in its "arbitrariness",
becoming more interested in "problem extraction,” as is the case in this
elusive representation of the well-known cave allegory attributed to Plato.
Magritte presents a painting within a painting, depicting the horizon as seen
through the opening of a dark cave lit by fire, a collection of
"simulacra.” This portrayal, therefore, is a diagnosis of the confusion
between reality and our representation of it. Magritte clarifies what he
expressed as the "human condition,” the title he chose for his painting:
“La condition humaine” 1935 (Fig2) – a leap into the deceptive world of
appearance.
Figure 2: the “La condition humaine”
by René Magritte (1935)
Diego Velázquez's 'Las Meninas' (1656) in (Fig3) has
spurred diverse interpretations, with Michel Foucault pondering its enigmatic
exchange of gazes in "The Order of Things." The painting invites
questions about who is viewing whom: Is it about the 'meninas', Infanta
Margarita, or the king and queen faintly reflected in a mirror? Velázquez's
gaze is directed at us, suggesting we might be the models, yet the exact
subject he's painting remains unseen. This prompts questions about absence and
presence. Are we the observers or the observed? Velázquez's work challenges not
just our aesthetic sense, but our cognitive abilities too. He incorporates
everyone — past, present, and future viewers — into his canvas, presenting a
profound relationship between humans and art, one perhaps questioning language.
Just as Michel Foucault says: The relationship between language and painting is
an infinite one. The word is incomplete and stands in the face of the visible,
striving in vain to surpass it. They cannot reduce each other; in vain, we say
what we see because what we see never dwells in what we say, and in vain, we
attempt to make others visualize through images, metaphors, and comparisons
what we are currently articulating. Therefore, in the face of this gray, obsessed,
and ever-repetitive language, drawings illuminate, proposing a solution for the
vague relationship between words and things.
Figure 3: the ‘Las Meninas' painting
(1656) by Diego Velázquez
Carrying this discussion from words as medium to their
abstract realm – words as material – Immanuel Kant's axiom suggests that all
spatial perceptions are a self-image in which content is separated from the
containing form or framework. Kant referred to this as the external relations
that the logical sense perceives as content. However, the point highlighted by
the Arabic thinker Jalal Al-Azm is that “Kant viewed space as a priori in
relation to the senses after drawing a sharp distinction between the image and
the content, defining the 'content' as the senses." Indeed, every
perception is a mental abstraction of an image of something. Therefore, the
content of the thing is an expression sensibly acceptable up to a certain extent.
The distinction between content and its formal image, despite seeming
arbitrarily meaningless, is sanctioned by Jalal Al-Azm with reservations, but
he finds it a reasonably acceptable rationale. He posits that the justification
for this separation hinges on two potential conditions. First, this
relationship should be necessary, meaning the image of space inherently and
necessarily corresponds to this content, and the content is intrinsically
suitable and compatible with this image. Only then would their relationship be
essential. Second, the relationship between the image and the content is
incidental, implying that their alignment is due to “coincidence” and not a
logical or philosophical necessity.
Every specific spatial content contained within a
substance consists of content and form that necessarily harmonize due to
inherent existential necessity. It's self-evident that the form of a specific
material or spatial content is not suitable for another content that differs in
its harmonious nature that one registered it in mind. The things perceived by
the mind are only those things where their image or external form harmonizes
with their material content. It is almost impossible to find a form that coincidentally
matches the material content of something without being determined and
accidentally associated with it. So, what does it mean for the relationship
between the image and the content to be not justified by logical or
philosophical necessity but to be mere coincidence? Do we need to subject all
natural harmony in the consonance between the image and content in phenomena,
places, and things in their existence to the factor of chance just to justify a
state of philosophical arbitrariness that makes perceiving the image suffice
without perceiving its content? Descartes and John Locke, in what is known in
philosophy as the principle of epistemological dualism, concluded more
logically, far from Kant's pure logic approach, that perceiving an object's image
is an implicit perception of its content in its entirety. Genuine perception
doesn't involve separating an object's content from its external attributes.
Berkeley's objection to them was not to separate the image from its original
content, but to say that full perception of a thing does not preclude
investigating beyond this initial preliminary perception. Perceiving something
doesn't mean knowing its true nature; perhaps he meant the essence hidden
behind external qualities. Kant then was pioneering in this perceptual and
conceptual sense, considering existence itself to be the essence that we cannot
perceive. Existentialists led by Husserl in phenomenology took this from him.
Another way to understand the various ideologies towards
such complex relations is also to explore how reality is perceived and
projected to be perceived differently might be found through the cultural
actions towards revolutions. As the industrial revolution neared its end, a
fresh perspective on art evolved, blending the mechanics of the human body with
machinery. During the mid-1800s to the interwar era, cities became hubs for
technology-driven objects, fostering new art forms, social environments, and
entertainment. This period marked a convergence of art and life via technology,
with a notable mechanization process influencing both the human body and
crafted artifacts (Fig4 and 5). Artists such as Fritz Kahn and Harold Wheeler attempted
to grasp the intricacies of the machine-body relationship, it's vital to
examine their varying interactions, from small devices to broad systems.
Everything, be it architecture, artifacts, or organisms, acts as linked
elements in this tapestry. Their fusion spawns pioneering creations. Such
intersections breed new synergies among diverse entities, leading to unique
movement and social patterns. By contrasting avant-garde art with new
technological and industrial trends, we can highlight artists who pursued more
abstract approach to the discourse of human and science such as Laszlo
Moholy-Nagy (and his work ‘vision in motion’) and Naum Gabo, who anchor their
work in the tangible mechanics of machines.
Figure 4: "The Wonders Within
Your Head" (1938) by Fritz Kahn
Figure 5: "Vision in Motion” by
Laszlo Moholy-Nagy
The discourse
on the impact of machines on art and drawings delves into the body's
metamorphosis into machinery and its artistic representation. It raises
questions like how art pictures the body's future. Rather than predict the
body's future, it's essential to study how drawings have historically portrayed
it amidst societal changes. A profound exploration can be found in Matthew
Barney's Cremaster Anatomies series, with roots in the 1993 Post-human
exhibition curated by Jeffrey Deitch. This exhibit forecasted body changes due
to biotechnological and medical advances, with art playing a pivotal role in
these transformations. The Pygmalion myth symbolizes the age-old allure of
merging human and artificial elements, an idea reinforced during the 19th
century's industrial era, viewing the body as machine-like. Over the 20th
century, this imagery evolved, reflecting technological influences on the human
form. The "post-human" term of the 1990s transitioned focus from
machinery to advanced bio-communication technologies. Within this context, this
study delves into Barney's portrayal of the body, situating it in the
technological landscape of the late 20th and early 21st centuries.
Herbert
Marcuse (1898 - 1979) argued that the modern industrial society curtailed the
artistic scope of imagination in favor of scientific and technical imagination,
which aligns with industrial progress. While valuing its potential to
revolutionize society, Marcuse emphasized rehabilitating imagination for its
vital role in human liberation. He believed that critical theory should stem
from man's tangible reality rather than solely from imagination. Marcuse noted
that true imaginative freedom mirrors the real potential for tangible freedom.
Modern society produces the 'one-dimensional man,' characterized by
technological rationality and materialistic uniformity, driven by material
progress, luxury, and consumption. This society embraces positivism, applying
natural science principles to humans and modeling reality quantitatively. It
also spawns vast institutions that control, guide, and objectify individuals
for pre-determined ends. To truly elevate humanity, we must re-engage with the
constrained imagination of modern man amidst technological advancements. This
engagement will drive innovation, enabling constructive interaction with social
realities, reclaiming the innate human essence overshadowed by modern progress
and its influence on imagination.
In examining media as an instrument for diverse forms of knowledge
construction, through which individuals discern the "real," it becomes
pivotal to analyze the socioeconomic shifts in association with machines,
buildings, and their representations. In his exploration of the history of
architectural regulation in the US, Michael Osman’s book “Modernism's Visible
Hand” delves into one facet of this discourse. He sheds light on the emergence
of a domestic economy dialogue in the United States during the mid-19th
century, a period marked by the advent of thermostat technology in homes. The
U.S. quickly embraced home electrification, largely due to Thomas Edison's
innovations, paving the way for an integrated network that incorporated
thermostats into architectural interiors. This catered to a specific individual
within the household: not the father or children, but the mother. She became
the orchestrator of the American interior condition, with "condition"
referring to the state of the household. With the thermostat's introduction,
her role evolved from a housekeeper to a household manager. As such, the
thermostat became the medium through which she seamlessly merged administration
with daily life. An examination of a thermostat advertisement (Fig6) unveils
the era's cultural focus on health, economy, and societal values. All these
themes converge in a singular linguistic gesture within the image: the text
emphasizes the need for "an automatic heat regulator" to ensure a
steady room temperature. An "even," "uniform temperature"
is portrayed as essential for both comfort and health, with
"sanitary" underscoring the promise of a pristine, hygienic living
space. In the ad, a female figure, representing the household manager, is
depicted adjusting the thermostat. The engagement and wedding rings on her
finger indicate the middle-class status of American society then. Below the
thermostat's image, the words "adjust here" specify her action, while
"it's automatic" beneath her hand emphasizes the device's
user-friendly nature—regulating the temperature demands minimal effort, akin to
simply activating the device.
Figure 6: "An
ad for an early home thermostat. (American Homes and Gardens 3; 1906)”
Bibliography
- Plato. "The Republic." Translated by G.M.A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1992.
- Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. "Phenomenology of Perception." Translated by Colin Smith. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1962.
- Freud, Sigmund. "The Interpretation of Dreams." Translated by James Strachey. New York: Basic Books, 2010.
- Deleuze, Gilles. "Difference and Repetition." Translated by Paul Patton. New York: Columbia University Press, 1994.
- Foucault, Michel. "The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences." New York: Pantheon Books, 1970.
- Heidegger, Martin. "Being and Time." Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row, 1962.
- Magritte, René. "The Treachery of Images" (1929).
- Velázquez, Diego. "Las Meninas." 1656.
- Kant, Immanuel. "Critique of Pure Reason." Translated by Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
- Descartes, René. "Meditations on First Philosophy." Translated by Donald A. Cress. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1993.
- Locke, John. "An Essay Concerning Human Understanding." Edited by Peter H. Nidditch. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.
- Berkeley, George. "A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge." Edited by Jonathan Dancy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.
- Husserl, Edmund. "Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology." Translated by W. R. Boyce Gibson. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1931.
- Moholy-Nagy, László. "Vision in Motion." Chicago: Paul Theobald, 1947.
- Barney, Matthew. "Cremaster Anatomies."
- Marcuse, Herbert. "One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society." Boston: Beacon Press, 1964.
- Osman, Michael. “Modernism's Visible Hand: Architecture and Regulation in America.” Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2018.